Albert Camus: From Absurd to Revolt : Beebagar Mumtaz

 


Albert Camus: From Absurd to Revolt

Beebagar Mumtaz 

Albert Camus, born on November 7, 1913, in Mondovi, Algeria, emerged as a towering figure in 20th-century literature and philosophy. Growing up in a French settler family in Algeria, his upbringing amidst the colonial tensions significantly influenced his worldview. Camus's early experiences of poverty and disenfranchisement shaped his profound sense of justice and empathy for the oppressed.

He began his career as a journalist, using his platform to highlight the injustices faced by Algerian Muslims under French colonial rule. Notably, Camus supported the French Popular Front's project to grant citizenship and voting rights to Algerian Muslims, articulating a powerful defense of their rights and condemning the systemic inequalities they endured.

Camus's political journey was marked by his membership in the Algerian Communist Party, driven by a desire to support the working-class Algerians. However, his unwavering support for Arab nationalist causes led to his expulsion when the party's stance shifted under Soviet influence, demonstrating his commitment to his principles despite political isolation.

During the Algerian War of Independence, Camus advocated for a civil truce, aiming to reduce violence and foster dialogue, a stance that garnered resistance from both sides but highlighted his dedication to peace and justice. His contemporaries, including Amar Ouzegane and Albert Memmi, recognized his sincere efforts and empathetic stance towards the Algerian people.

Beyond his political activism, Camus's literary and philosophical works, such as "The Myth of Sisyphus" and "The Rebel," explore themes of absurdity, rebellion, and the search for meaning in an indifferent universe. His vision of rebellion as a pursuit of unity and justice, contrasted with the totalitarian impulses of Soviet ideology, underscores his belief in balancing freedom and justice.

Albert Camus's legacy is one of a principled intellectual and humanist, navigating the complexities of colonial and postcolonial Algeria with empathy and integrity. His life and work continue to resonate, offering profound insights into the struggle for justice and the human condition. Camus passed away on January 4, 1960, but his contributions to literature and philosophy endure, making him a seminal figure whose thoughts remain relevant in contemporary discourse.

Camus the Existentialist?

Many among critics and readers of Camus see him as an existentialist or a Sartrean. And this cannot be wrong given the time of his writings on human needs and existence. It was a time at which whoever chose to write on human existence was considered an existentialist and particularly a Sartrean. To read Camus in view of his ‘existentialism’, if I consider him one of their kinds, his writings shall produce not such an enormous effect since Camus himself admitted that he was neither a Sartrean nor an existentialist. Interestingly, Sartre has also refused to consider Camus an existentialist in his journalistic writings twice. In other words, to insist that an existentialist writes on human existence and his needs then Camus says in an interview, ‘’if one is an existentialist because one poses the problems of human needs, then all literature, from Montaigne to Pascal’’ is the literature of just existentialists. However, he was a critic of existentialism, not an opponent, and proclaimed that existentialists ‘‘defy what crushes them’’ which is the main theme in his book The Myth of Sisyphus. In a review to Sartre’s novel Nausea, he says human find their meanings when he finds no meaning in his life and this is the beginning of his absurdist.  In other words, the absurdist in the realization that life is absurd cannot be an end to life but just a beginning. And this is the starting point the greatest minds have started from. This discovery, he says, cannot lead one to controversy or to a conclusion but tries to draws results and directions from it. One of the main reasons Camus doesn’t align himself with existentialist is because he believes the existentialists and Marxists have an end in point. From Marx to Hegel, history is a transcendental value system, an absolute value that is its end and hence history is ‘totalizing’. However, whether existentialism believes in such a system is uncertain but Sartre who was an existentialist and later admitted being a Marxist at the same time makes the point considerable.

Literature, therefore, suggests that Camus was not an existentialist but an absurdist. His absurdist is the man who knows his conditions of life and accepts his efforts in overcoming them without any absolute point kept in mind. It is not science or metaphysics world that Camus locates his hero in, he clearly defies the hypothesis of science and proclaims that everything related to me and the externality that I can touch and feel exist. He says, ‘This heart within me I can feel, and I judge that it exists. This world I can touch and I likewise judge that it exists. There ends all my knowledge and the rest is construction’. Sartre calls his absurdism that existence where the body nauseates and finds no external justification to his life. However, Camus’s absurdism is not a denial of all values, it doesn’t lead to what Camus calls nihilism or philosophical suicide like Kierkegaard. His absurdist finds belief in faith which Camus says is false since he says we begin claiming that the world has no meaning and then search for meaning in its depth is a statement based on some kind of end that might justify the means of your existence or perhaps it might not justify and one ends committing ‘philosophical suicide’. Camus says the absurdist has meaning so far as it is not agreed to. He is filled with scorn and suffering and this doesn’t lead him to defiance but accepts it as such. His absurdist is Sisyphus who is wretched and is scorned by Gods for stealing fire and has ended up in a condition of suffering in which he moves the stone to the top of the mountain and the stone ends up falling due to its weight. Carroll suggests that it is clear that Sisyphus accomplishes nothing by being scorned by God and taking stone to a height but it is, in fact, the something of art. So, at this point, Camus’s hero is happy Sisyphus, who is scorned by Gods, rejects suicide, holds jealousy to this condition and is committed to his fate. In other words, Camus’ Sisyphus is a happy man who is not joining with others but accepts him as him in his own condition. But, given the political and social conditions of 1942 and afterwards, Camus began to engage in political commitments, for instance, joining French resistance in 1943 and becoming editor in chief of the paper Combat, suggest that Sisyphus is Camus’s first step towards revolt that will later form a general political and social commitment.  

Moreover, Camus continues to produce writings on absurdism by taking his hero to the next stage of his philosophy which I undoubtedly believe is no less than a philosophical talk. His next work, The Outsider (Also known as The Stranger in some translations) was also published in the same year in which his The Myth of Sisyphus was printed. This book is very popular, almost read by a good number or at least have heard about it, and it received the Nobel Prize in Literature. This book is about which post colonialism takes its talk on different aspects of book and mocks the author for being Eurocentric and French-Algerian racist. For instance, Edward Said in his book Culture and Imperialism says the fact the Meursault (the protagonist) kills an unnamed Arab and is executed by court for showing social non-conformity on his mother’s funeral is Camus being racist against Arabs. Now, this criticism is not so strong given Camus’ other writings are. On the other hand, there can be a different interpretation of the novel within view his other works include statements or articles on Algerian people, that we will be looking at later. The act of killing Arab takes Meursault to court where people laugh at him and the judge makes him concerned not with the murder and the first bullet but is interested to know why the other bullets were fired. And the prosecutor is interested to know about his behavior on his mother’s funeral since he was normal and unwept. This makes Camus’s work a masterpiece that is not being racist but is a critique on French administration and her courts dealing with Arabs. In other words, the execution of Meursault serves as a formality for killing an Arab that is a powerful criticism of racism of French-Algerian justice, where an individual kills an Arab and is executed for not crying on his mother’s funeral.  In addition, it also serves as critique on state and her authority for shaping such a society which is based on deceit and lies. Camus says, ‘‘lying is not only what is not true. It is also, in fact, especially, saying more than is true and, in the case of human heart, saying more than one feels’’. On the other hand, Meursault is a man who is honest with his absurdist mind; he doesn’t want to lie about his feelings. It is in this context we must see that the absurd does not allow him to see good and bad and right and wrong in social contexts. When he is asked to admit to his sin, he replies of no having such knowledge what a sin is and says that he was informed that he is guilty and so he is paying for it and there is nothing else that he could offer.

Furthermore, Camus’s thoughts move from nihilism to hope. In his publication of a play, Caligula, after two years of his first books, he tries to show using his characters, Cherea and Scipio, that the absurd does not lead to nihilist thoughts. He questions, ‘‘what lay the difference? Simply that you readily accepted despair and I never yielded to it’’. Camus knows that to be aware of an absurd behavior does not mean to have hope but this is in this hopelessness that does not lead to despair. In other words, the absurd admits himself to a total absence of hope but unlike Kafka and Kierkegaard Camus says this absence of hope must not lead to despair, or in his words, ‘philosophical suicide’.  In a conversation in his play, Cherea rejects what the nihilist Caliguila says, he says Caliguila departs from the ethic of the absurd or of his book The Myth of Sisyphus when he says ‘‘I believe that some actions are more admirable than others’’. What Camus is trying to show that the absurd behavior must never transform itself into nihilist thoughts where despair is valued and therefore Cherea asks Scipio to take part in his assassination. Scipio’s father was tortured and killed by the emperor, Caliguila, and this makes the assassination more possible and legitimate (if I may use this word) than ever since Cherea makes sense of the scene with these words: ‘‘Caligula has taught you to despair. And to have instilled despair into a young heart is fouler than the foulest crimes he has committed up to now. I assure you that alone would justify me in killing him out of hand.’’ Using the writings that reflect back to Camus’s thoughts, it could be concluded that his absurd is not nihilistic. Where ‘‘nihilism is not only despair and negation but, above all, the desire to despair and negate’’, the absurd ‘‘does not liberate, it binds. It does not authorize all actions’’. So, nihilism, as it can be seen, is the rejection of all human values whereas the absurd has the possibility of value.

I rebel, therefore, we exist

Camus takes his philosophy to such a height in the rebel where he gives the absurd a reason to revolt. This revolt shall be based on solidarity and on communication. Communication indicts solidarity since there is possibility of saying what is true, true in a sense it is common to all men or I should be using Gramsci’s common sense, and listening  to what others say. Therefore, Camus believes an absurd mind must never be certain because certainty gives the hope for an envisioned tomorrow. Based on this certainty, he gives his conclusions on Marx’s historical particularism (though the word was used by Engels and never by Marx himself) in the latter part of the book, The Rebel that was published in 1948.

In Marxist analysis, communism is the end point of human prosperity and equality. Camus says Marxism resembles like Christian Messiasim which has a certain beginning point and definite end point. Marx, he claims replaced Hegelian dialectics that of class consciousness with economic autonomy and spirit with communism or a classless society. He says, ‘‘the most eloquent eulogy of capitalism was made by its greatest enemy. Marx is only anti-capitalist in so far as capitalism is out of date’’. However, what Camus means is not that Marx is contradictory but that Marx puts everything at stake in the realm of production and unlike Hegel, he also diminishes reason and spirit for the sake of material in history. Indeed, Camus is not worried for he dismissed reason and spirit and replaced it with economy and material, but that he makes a certain end point of history which is directly against historical rebellion (Historical rebellion, he argues, is rooted in the appeal to value of freedom and justice, where freedom is driving force of all revolutions and justice is inconceivable in the rebel’s mind). This he says on the basis of particularly Russian communism and Lenin’s revolution. He differentiates between fascism and Russian communism by calling former ‘‘the exaltation of executioner by executioner’’ and latter ‘’the exaltation of the executioner by the victims’’. Fascism tries to liberate some men and subjugate the others while Russian communism liberated all men by enslaving them all. He called the cornerstone of Soviet ideology ‘‘rational state terrorism’’. Furthermore, he says that Russian communism is totally different from that of Marx and Engel’s because Russian communism wanted a classless society which she did not get and therefore suggested that either Marx is wrong or the revolution has betrayed the theory on which case Lenin and later Stalin chose the former.  Lenin believed, Says Camus, ‘’only in the revolution an in the virtues of expediency’’. For instance, he says, ‘’One must be prepared for every sacrifice, to use if necessary every stratagem, ruse, illegal method, to be determined to conceal the truth, for the sole purpose of penetrating the labor unions... and of accomplishing, despite everything, the communist task’’. According to Camus, the ends must not justify the means and vice versa, in case that happens, that will be the beginning of dictatorship and end of rebellion.  ‘‘From of point of view, it is only nihilism – pure movement that aims at denying everything that is not itself…The end of history is not an exemplary or perfectionist value; it is an arbitrary and terrorist principle’’, says Camus. The reality of Russian Revolution, though it lays claim to be just was in fact based on ‘‘procession of violence and injustice’’.

Camus chose rebellion over revolution because he believes the revolution would triumph in dictatorship and would lose human values.  Rebel is a person who says ‘no’, and at the say time saying ‘yes’ to this affirmation that this would is indifferent to me and other human beings and this indifference is the case of human condition; therefore, I must survive in it, without being a victim of philosophical suicide. This survival shall prove to the truth of humanity where humanity is the community of we, whose human condition is same and must rebel against it to overcome it without having an envisioned tomorrow in the absurdist mind. This shall engulf the absurdist mind in nihilism if it leads to some point in end, a definite end for which the struggle is waged.  In other words, communication and unity is the basis of rebellion whereas certainty and totality are against it. Certainty and totality diminish the conversation between men where one passes instructions to other without listing to him in return. ‘‘It is not Mr. Hitler who can decide that what is true and what is not’’, he says. Only common consciousness can serve the interest of human values and strengthen the solidarity of the people, else whatever done in the absence of communication and common value would result in mass killing and destruction. Camus believes only in human terms and this is where meaning of a life is achieved. He says,                                                                                                                                                                                                ‘I don’t know whether this world has a meaning that transcends it. But I know that I do not know that meaning and that it is impossible for me just now to know it. What can a meaning outside my condition mean to me? I can understand only in human terms.

In short, this understanding is possible when there is communication and communication is truth without which neither rebel would strive or the human condition.  

Camus and Political Violence

In the last section of the Rebel, Camus is concerned with murder and he insists that a rebel cannot kill without being ready to die. His violence or I should be saying he has a kind of limited intensity of violence for his hero, the rebel. For instance, so many of us have died, so many of us are disappeared, so many of us are homeless and are harassed on daily basis and so much of what has been a place for our memories and happiness has been destroyed in the name of development that is for exploitative purposes; people had started rebelling against it from the first day because everything is not justifiable, they say, then so must be the case with these rebellions that they must be cautious to make everything  not justifiable on their behalf, since they started to rebel against injustice and equality. Camus is against political violence caused by bourgeois and revolutionary because he claims both of them justify their means for their ends. He defines ‘bourgeois’ account of political violence as the refusal to recognize the dilemma highlighted by this violence. On the other hand, keeping in mind the book by Merleau-Ponty’s Humanism and Terror in which the writer says, ‘’we ought to prefer revolutionary violence because it has a future of humanism’’, Camus says, violence is necessary, necessary on the point of making history nothing but ‘‘a continuous violation of everything in man which protests against injustice’’. This violence breaks the solidarity and results in unending violence even after the revolution has taken place, or it might be one of the pitfalls that Fanon had warned in his book, The Wretched of Earth. The rebel’s act of killing breaks his solidarity with human condition and it becomes his end of existence. However, Camus does not mean that there should not be violence at any cost, there should be if it is necessary, necessary in a sense proposed by the following conditions.

·       The victim must be a tyrant.

·       The act must be discriminate.

·       The assassin must accept full responsibility of the action.

·       There is no less violent alternative other than assassination.

Camus limits his political violence in his famous play, The Just Assassins by the character of Kaliayev. Kaliayve waits in the Moscow Street for the Grand Duke Sergius Alexandrovitch Romanov, the Tsar’s uncle and governor of Moscow, to throw a bomb inside his carriage when he passes. However, when he says that the Duke is not alone, his wife and niece and nephew are also with him, he aborts the mission. All of his associates agreed with him except Stephen who believed a revolutionary man must never be sentimental to children and women. But, for Camus, this would mean the end of rebellion and human condition and solidarity. After two days, the Duke is killed and Kaliayev stands there and accepts responsibility for the attack and death of the Duke. In other words, Camus’s political violence can be defined as ‘life for a life theory’ on which much criticism is based. For instance, Camus wants to strain the blood by shedding more blood by understanding political violence to be an eye of an eye. Phillip Tody says to suggest that all rebels must commit suicide after their services in the name of revolution is an unwise suggestion, and ‘‘no political organization fighting against a tyranny could possibly succeed if its leaders follow Kaliayev’s path’’. Now, this criticism is very harsh, harsh in a sense if Camus is not understood properly. What Camus is suggestion using the character of Kaliayev that after the killing is done, the killer must accept full responsibility of the action, he should be willing to die if he has decided to kill someone and this act of killing must be a ‘personal responsibility’ and an immediate risk. It is nicely put in words by Simone Weil,

              ‘’To keep the love of life intact within us; never to inflict death without accepting it for ourselves. Supposing  the life of X…were linked with our own so that the two bodies had to be simultaneous, should we still wish him to die? If with our whole body and soul we desire life and if nevertheless without lying, we can reply ‘’yes’’, then we have the right to kill.’’

Importantly, this is not enough to kill, the admission of killing someone because of not fearing death is not enough until the above four conditions are not met. Therefore, murder cannot be legitimized, not at least easily, until it is international law or a revolutionary force which fight against unjust and dictatorship and replace the old law with new. Therefore, Camus believes that Russian revolution changed from revolutionary violence to state terrorism. Furthermore, Camus says, ‘‘[international] law is made and remade by governments, that is, by the executive. We are therefore in a regime of international dictatorship’’. In fact, rebellion and murder are contradictory in themselves since rebellion is a protest against death and murder of people. Therefore, Camus limits the violence of his rebel because the latter understands human condition and is a part of it to overcome suffering and difficulties in social disorders. In short, Camus is not so much concerned with killings and murders of the people but the ideological manifestations or rationalizations implied on them. Whether France and USA rationalize killing in Vietnam or the former massacre people in the streets of Algeria is not a phenomenon that can be defended and reasoned since it involves taking lives of people. ‘‘I also condemn the use of terrorism which is exercised in the streets of Algeria, for example,’’ says Camus, ‘’and which could one day strike my mother and family’’. This is to the problem of Algeria I shall turn to now.

Reflections on the guillotine

‘Reflections on the guillotine’ was published in 1957 when the French-Algerian administration was actively executing Arabs. Camus recalls one of the memories that his father witnessed during the execution of an Arab. The Arab had killed a complete family and was arrested and executed in front of the people to know the consequences of acting against the state and (her people?). The father wanted to look in the eyes of the victim since he wanted to know how it felt like killing a family and being executed. At the time of the execution, when his head was cut off, it was to be put in the basket but the basket remained closed before the head was put and the father could see in the eyes of the executed head. He saw in the eyes of the executed as if the eyes were demanding forgiveness which had closed later without being provided some. The father returned home and felt very depressing. This incident compelled Camus to quest for representations and misrepresentations.

Camus says there is some innocence in every guilty person. We get news from the media that the law has paid his debt by killing the criminal who is, no matter who, produced by his own society. Every society has its own criminals. The law that is used to punish those who create chaos and disorder is based on deterrence argument and retributivism. The latter is based on exemplary way of punishment in order to bring to the other members of the society that people shall be punished for committing crimes, crimes that are even not committed. It is used to create fear and chaos in the society to follow law no matter what the consequences of its obedience mean. This law is used to get Gramsci’s consent from the people to act on the lines of prescribed directions provided by the state. However, the former, the law of deterrence is as old as an eye for an eye; it is used for revenge. Both of these laws still persist in the states that have taken shape even after the death of Camus.

In order to get better view of these laws, I am returning to a sociologist that spoke well about it. Emile Durkheim in his book The Division of Labour says the law might change its shape but in the end the essential elements of the punishment remain the same, i.e. to take revenge. People who committed crimes, crimes in a sense that hurt the beliefs and sentiments of the people, were punished according to the intensity of public offence, for it has tried to break the collective consciousness. For example, in modern societies, offences such as murder are often less severely punished if it doesn’t concern the collective representation of the people, the people being busy in their own lives as a break between interactions with other people, hence a gap between collective representations of the people. In simpler societies, religion played a key role in biding people and those who went against the teachings of the religion were killed. However, in capitalist era, the societies are differentiated and population has grown dense, hence there grew a need of the structure that would represent the collective consciousness of the people. This structure was the state. Alike body where the brain guides different organs to function, in societies, this act is performed by the state. So, any act that may perhaps have not hurt the sentiments or collective representation of the people, the people being unaware of it, the state considers it one and punishes the actor. The state that was designed to represent the people is suppressing the people for its own representation and improving its police and military. The state become above the individual whereas it was designed to be below the people in order to represent them rightly. Such was the case in Algeria where the French administration took harsh steps against Arabs that though were in majority and perhaps right in their demands. Therefore, Camus says, ‘‘our society must now defend herself not so much as against individual as against the state’’. 

Camus and Sartre on Violence

Interesting is the time period when two friends turned against each other intellectually. After Camus wrote and published The Rebel, Jeanson wrote a lengthy review in one of the journals of Sartre criticizing Camus for being Hegel’s “beautiful soul” who prefers to remain pure and untouched by reality. In fact, Camus’s book was not so much based on historical materialism than on rationalization of murder but Jeanson summed it up in these words: “All evil is found in history and all good outside of it”. However, that is not what Camus had meant but in fact the total opposite of it. He says, “It is written there, for there who wish to read, that he who believes only in history marches toward terror and that he who doesn’t believe in it at all authorizes terror”. He writes to Sartre “Your colleague writes as if he were ignorant of the fact that Marxism no more inaugurated the revolutionary tradition than the German inaugurated philosophy”.

What Camus thinks about violence and what kind of violence is permitted in his realm is sort of a limited one that we have already seen briefly. Moreover, it is not easy to put overall a review of talks that Sartre have had about  violence but what will be written is a struggle of summarization. Ronald Santoni has provided a detailed overview of the writings of Sartre on violence beginning from their ontological study in ‘Being and Nothingness’ to the last controversial talks in ‘Hope New Interviews’ that were published shortly after Sartre’s death. In his other works, importantly Critique of Dialectical Reason volume I and II and the unpublished ‘Rome Lecture’ provide intensive understanding of Sartre’s ideas on violence. In Being and Nothingness, Sartre identifies conflict as the “essence of relations between consciousnesses”. It creates between I and the other a distinction that begins recognition between actors. He says, “It is necessary above all that I be the one who is not the Other, and it is in this very negation…that I make myself be and the Other arises as the Other”. At other times, he defines violence “in terms of purposive human activity aroused by conditions of material scarcity”.  Furthermore, Sartre’s system works dialectically that is the background to CDR’s description of the dialectical movement from individual praxis (individual working on nature to complete his needs) to the common or group praxis (the group working to fulfill the needs) that he calls “group-in-fusion”. Now, the individual can be the victim of alienation in the group that is why Sartre suggests a practical device that is an oath or pledge that “binds the group in permanence”. Sartre declares this oath to be “a statute of violence” that finds its origin in fear and its strength through violence. “To swear is to say, as a common individual, I demand that you kill me if I secede [or betray the group]. And this demand has no other goal but to establish Terror in me against the fear of the enemy.” According to Sartre, terror far from destroying a group unites the group in pledge. It constitutes the ‘primary unity’ of the pledged group.  In CDR, violence is interpreted as the recreation of a lost right, as a counter violence, violence against the freedom of right that is why it presents itself justified. For Sartre, the most legitimate violence is found only in anti-colonial violence. That is why, he writes in the preface of The Wretched of the Earth, “A freedom fighter’s weapon is his humanity”.

In response to Camus’ theoretical implications of violence, Sartre says if there is only one way to save humanity and it involves means incompatible with human world , isn’t action with humanity as its end impossible?  According to the so-called ‘scale metaphor’ where ends and means are weighted against one another in determining whether to take an action or not, involving morality, is directly rejected by Sartre and he says ends and means are both constitutive parts of human world, where the end synthesizes or totalizes the means [and where] the end does not come after the means, but “pervades their use, keeps them together as means and even guides them”.  He says “revolutionary praxis requires no external justification” and “all means are good except those that denature the end”.

In addition, the oath that the individual takes in order to become part of the ‘group-in-fusion’, the individual must pretend to know something and then unlearn that something if it creates disadvantages for the party. In simple words, Sartre believes that the ‘collective consciousness’ that has been formed in the members’ minds, there should be no such thing as lies that might disturb the party’s comfort. In case, there is lying in rebel’s attitude and talks, this rebel shall create ‘a lied-to and lying mankind’. However, on the other hand, he says in war, every revolutionary party is at war, and therefore, the soldiers do not have to know the whole truth of what the behind the scenes might be. Now, this is interesting, interesting in a sense that Camus says lying is what the man tells the other man more than he can feel. What, I believe, Sartre insists on saying is the same. A revolutionary man cannot be told something that denatures the revolutionary end. “All means are good except those that denature the end”, he says. Nonetheless, he puts some conditions in order for the terror to be revolutionary voice for justice. The following are his conditions:

·       ‘If terror is used only as a means to produce yet another exploitative system or to keep human beings in a state of sub humanity, it must not be permitted’.

·       Terror is permissible only ‘if those who employ Terror can prelude and therefore avoid all ideologies of Terror’.

·       Terror is permissible ‘only if no justification of Terror is offered other than its necessity’.

·       Terror is permissible ‘only if Terror has its ‘origins in the masses’’.

In the ‘Rome lecture’, Sartre declared that his violence is based on ‘socialist morality’. This is morality that “is a set of guidelines for securing conditions of concrete freedom that will make moral conduct on such a universal standard possible” at some point in the future.

Interestingly, The Just Assassins that we have seen in the paragraphs above was in fact a response of a play that Sartre had written a year before Camus’ play was published. It was Sartre’s Dirty Hands in 1948 that compelled Camus to write his play or perhaps it can be one of the factors. In an interview, Sartre says “politics requires us to get our hands dirty”. One of the characters in Dirty Hands, Hoederer says that revolution “is not a question of virtue but of effectiveness”. He further says:

              “How you cling to your purity, young man! How afraid you are to soil your hands! All right, stay     pure! What good will you do? Why did you join us? Purity is an idea for a yogi or a monk. You            intellectuals and bourgeois anarchists use it as pretext for doing nothing. To do anything, to               remain motionless, arms at your sides, wearing kid gloves. Well, I have dirty hands. Right up to      the elbows. I have plunged them in filth and blood. But what do you hope? Do you think you can               govern innocently?”

One of the examples in which Hoederer gets his hands dirty is a conversation with the other character, Hugo. Hugo when joining the (Communist) Proletarian Party says, “for the first time I saw men who didn’t lie to other men”. In contrast, Hoedered says “we have always told lies, just like any other party…I’ll lie when I must…I wasn’t the one who invented lying. It grew out of a society divided into classes, and each one of us has inherited it from birth. We shall not abolish lying by refusing to tell lies, but by using every means at had to abolish classes”. Although Sartre was not against communists and wrote on their behalf but most communists considered this work as anti-communist. In an interview with Sartre, Paola Caruso says Sartre chose Hoederer as his revolutionary type by saying Hoederer “is the man I’d like to be if I were a revolutionary”. In contrast to Camus, who believes in sticking to principles and refusing to lie for it is the same as respecting and loving people, for Sartre acting on principle dictated being true to long-term ends. Sartre believes that Camus chose idealism over realism by choosing ‘clean hands’ and showcasing himself what Jeanson has called ‘beautiful soul’. What in fact Camus’ clean hands is, is entering into war without actually desiring it. For example, France did not start World War II and it was Germans that started occupying France, so the latter had no option but to kill and protect them. However, this cannot be called ‘defensive strategy’.

Lastly, both Sartre and Camus had different perspectives on between morality and politics. Sartre blames Camus for locating his morality outside history and says: “You became violent and terrorist when History-which you rejected- rejected you in turn…Your morality first changed into moralism. Today, it is only literature. Tomorrow perhaps it will be immorality”. The difference between the both is Sartre subordinated morality into politics while Camus subordinated politics into morality. Sartre clearly spoke about his rejection of moralism by admitting that “you do it because it works, and…you evaluate it according to its efficacity rather than some vague notions having to do with morality, which would only slow things up”. He says although Marxism had a morality long before but “it’s Mao who clarified it and gave it flesh”. The latter point is clarified in the below passage quoted from Sartre’s writings:

              ‘For the Maoists…everywhere that revolutionary violence is born among the masses, it is immediately and profoundly moral. This is because the workers, who have up to the point been        the objects of capitalist authoritarianism, become the subjects of their own history, even if only for a moment…Yet even though the economic and political motives of the exploitations of               popular violence are obvious, the explosions cannot be explained except by the fact that these            motives were morally appreciated by the masses. That is, the economic and political motives               helped the masses to understands what is the highest immorality-the exploitation of man by    man. So when the bourgeois claims that his conduct is guided by a ‘humanistic’ morality-work,          family, nation-he is only disguising his deep-seated immorality and trying to alienate the       workers: he will never be moral. Whereas the workers and the country people, when they revolt, are completely moral because they are not exploiting anyone.’

Memi’s Well-meaning Coloniser                                                                                                                                       

The attitude of Albert Camus in regards to Algerian war of independence and French occupation is very controversial. It is not controversial in a sense that the both sides were not clear in their stance, controversial because for Camus’ background lies in the Algerian land. Camus was born there and his parents and two of his grandparents lived there. Hence, Camus was culturally pied-noir which means the presence of Mediterranean European cultures in Algeria affected him in a great degree. And Camus’ conception of Mediterranean culture is one that which is based on internationalism and humanist ‘principle’ of ‘man’. However, postcolonial criticism rejects the notion of this culture and criticizes Camus for being ‘Eurocentric’. One of such critics is Cruise O’Brien who says:

              ‘…This truth of a Mediterranean culture exists and manifests itself on every point: unity, facility      of learning one Latin language when one knows another; two, unity of origin, prodigious collectivism of the Middle Ages, order of knights, order of religious feudalities, etc.’

Camus claims in a lecture that the Mediterranean is based on Hellenic rather than Roman and as a result of his misconception, O’ Brien says majority of the inhabitants in Algeria are Arab-speaking people and treats Camus’s lecture as a consequence of having a Western point of view. In fact, it is stated that post colonialism treat Camus’s work based on some textual selectivity while ignoring the other that had been written on behalf of Algeria. For instance, in December, 1936, the French Popular Front published a project in order to provide French citizenship and voting rights to 20,000 Algeria Muslims. However, the bill got cancelled before even reaching at the chambers of the deputies because most of the members of the Parliament threatened to resign if the bill was to pass. As a result of this, Camus published a manifesto defending the plan by claiming that “culture could not live where dignity was dying, and a civilization could not flourish under laws which crush it…One cannot speak of culture in a country where 900,000 inhabitants were denied schools, or of civilization, when it is a question of a people weakened by unprecedented poverty and destitution and bullied by emergency legislation and inhuman regulations”.  In addition, he says the only way to restore the dignity of Muslim masses was to allow expressing themselves. Although the plan was an attempt to assimilate Arab inhabitants but Camus’s support in shape of his written manifesto is a call for the rights of the Arabs.

In addition, postcolonial criticism also ignores Camus expulsion from Algerian Communist Party. Camus had joined the party in 1935 in order to be close with working class of Algerian people for whose cause the party worked. He insisted that his role was that of ‘recruiting Arab Militants and having them join a nationalist organization’ which was Messali Hadj’s Etoile Nord Africain (ENA). However, PCA stopped supporting the pro-Arab militancy when it was instructed by Moscow.  In a short time, the comrades of the ENA were arrested by French government as a policy designed and forwarded by the communist party. Camus objected to this policy and as a result of which he was summoned to headquarters in order to change his position. Instead, Camus said, “observing that the party had been right to support Muslim nationalists earlier and it did not have the right to discredit them now, thereby playing into the hands of the colonialists”.  Camus was expelled from the party and in his after-party days, he did not join any other political party.

Contrary to postcolonial critics, particularly Edward Said and O’Brien, if we discuss Camus with his contemporaries, Amar Ouzegance and Albert Memmi, we get very positive compliments expressing Camus’ attitude to Algerian occupation and French suppression. Amar Ouzegance, who was the Secretary General of PCA at the time of expulsion of Camus, and a senior member of FLN during the war of Algeria against France, believed Camus to be “like the Arabised Europeans who had accepted and identified themselves with Arab, with Algerian”. He regarded Camus to be more revolutionary and clear-sighted than his peers that were active in trying to assimilate Arab people. Furthermore, Albert Memmi in his canonical text, The Colonizer and the Colonized, regards Camus as being “the colonizer who refuses” and “the colonizer of good will”. However, it is not clear what he meant by this long before he described Camus’ attitude in an article. In the article, he says:

              ‘It must be understood that his position is hardly easy: it is difficult, both emotionally and     intellectually, to have one’s entire on the side being morally condemned. One might regret,     perhaps, that Camus was unable to really go beyond the clan, to place himself from the outset       on the level of the universal. But I should add immediately that had he done so, it would not               have ended there: he would have been even more hated by his own community. In fact,      Camus’s situation is such that it was guaranteed to reap the suspicions of the colonized, the        indignation of the left-wing metropolitan French and the anger of his own community. From this            springs his silence, or semi-silence, for one is dealing here with a false impression: Camus has          spoken [on Algeria], and more frequently than many others. But his situation is such that he can               only succeed in angering everybody. Camus embodies, quite accurately, what I have called the            colonizer of good-will. It is an ambiguous role, but I must stress that it is neither comic nor               contemptible.‘

Clearly, Memmi disagreed with Camus’s version of justice for the Algerian people but he understood the paradoxical location of him. For example, he declared in 1985 that Sartre who had written the preface of his book, The Colonizer and the Colonized, “had really understood, or rather felt, our problems’’, “with Camus, I had the sense of being immediately on the same emotional and sentimental register’’.

Furthermore, it is common for masses to hold protests during the war of independence in order to record their suffering and plea to the people to hear them. Such was an accident in the towns of Serif and Guelma where the Algerian people turned into protests and riots began as a result of which one hundred Europeans were killed. As a reaction or perhaps as a revenge of these violent protests, the French Army killed thousands of Muslims (some estimate that at least seventy-five thousand) were killed.  Some critics of Algerian war of independence mark this incident as the beginning of the insurrection against French occupation. For example, the Berber poet Kateb Yacine observed “I was sixteen years old and I have never forgotten the shock of that merciless butchery which took thousands of Muslim lives. There at Serif the iron of nationalism entered my soul”. The media remained silent over it and people like Sartre never brought it in print until his publication of the preface to Fanon’s The Wretched of Earth. However, Camus had just returned from Algeria spending two weeks there covering 1500 miles of the country and almost recording everything that were later published in a series of articles in Combat beginning on 13 May.

In these articles, Camus accuses French administration for being ignorant about the people of Algeria and says for French, Algeria might not exist but for the later the former exists. He writes about humanitarian, economic and political crisis in Algeria, of the continued failure of the French to address and resolve the issues of Algerian people and without realization of the government that “most Algerians are experiencing a famine”. France needs to be conquered again so that it doesn’t feel low in helping its people by realizing that “people are suffering from hunger and demanding justice. We cannot remain indifferent to their suffering because’’, alluding to Nazi occupation, “we have experienced it ourselves’’.  Although Camus did not create a fictionalized Algeria where the French justice had already existed, O’ Brian accuses Camus for remaining such an author; beside, what Camus wanted was justice to be provided to Algerian people, he asked and pressed the French administration to not remain indifferent to their pleas.

Moreover, one of the other articles that is very popular in respect of the time and the demands it tries to meet from French and FLN was ‘Call for a Civil Truce’. Camus wrote this article as a manifesto since Charles Poncet and his former comrade in the PCA, Amar Ouzegane asked him to write one. This meeting was conducted on 22 January, 1956 at which Camus was the keynote speaker. Camus’s speech contained what he had been writing in newspapers. He said a civil truce is necessary since it will lessen the amount of combatants being killed on both sides and create a healthy environment for discussion for the solution of Algerian problem.

On the contrary, when Camus visits Algeria, he is ‘barracked by the Europeans’ and ‘largely ignored by Muslims’.  Camus considered the only solution to the problem of Algeria was a ‘civil truce’ which was rejected and ignored by postcolonial critics though it was an effort of great appraisal. People like Sartre and Simon Beauvoir mocked Camus for being apolitical and presenting such a useless solution. In fact, Camus’s solution was possible. When Germaine Tillion, an ethnologist who started working in Algeria from 1930s to 1958, said that she met the FLN leader, Saadi Yacef, and the leader told her that she promised that she would stop targeting civilians if the French ceased killing imprisoned Algerian ‘patriots’. Camus stopped working for the future of Algeria from that moment on when he saw the reaction of the people after being convinced that the people hated him for presenting such a truce proposal.  He told his friends Jean Daniel and Mouloud Feroun that:

              ‘’The repression by the French is without justification, without excuses…it is necessary to say the            same thing, if we are fighting for justice, about the methods of the FLN who see in every French   Individual living in Algeria a representation of French colonial oppression…It I necessary to fight            for the truce, for the end to the massacre of innocent individuals, in order to establish the     political and moral conditions which will finally permit dialogue. And if we no longer have               influence over either side, perhaps it is necessary to remain silent for a while.

              When two of our brothers engage in a fight without mercy, it is criminal madness to excite one or the other of them. Between wisdom reduced to silence and madness which shouts itself         hoarse, I prefer the virtues of silence. Yes when speech managers to dispose without remorse of           the existence of others, to remain silent is not a negative attitude.’’

Unity and totality

The rebellion is based on the condition that it is based on unity. Without unity, the rebel loses its authentic form and transforms into dictatorship. The idea of ‘unity’ comes from Hegel which is ‘’in effect nothing other than the ancient dream of unity common to both believers and rebels, but projected horizontally onto an earth deprived of God’’. Furthermore, Camus says it is a risk to concentrate everything for a history that might be based on false destinies. History can only be observed from outside and therefore it can only be measured and calculated through the lens of the God.

Now, the idea of ‘totality’ is very scattered whenever we study or hear someone say something about Soviet ideology and Russian revolution. In fact, Marx scholar Kevin Anderson (1995) suggests that it was Lenin who introduced the idea of ‘totality’ into Marxist discourse. Similarly, Camus is exactly claiming the same to be true when he says that it is not communism that contains the idea of totality but the Soviet ideology that has spread it into Marxism. Before industrialism emerged, man was subjected to divinity and the revolutionary tradition then subjected man into historical evolution where he takes residue in the party. Rebellion “in its original authenticity’’ does not justify “any purely historical concept’’. Its “demand is unity’’, whereas “historical revolution’s demand is totality’’. “Historical revolution starts from an absolute negation and condemns itself to every form of servitude in order to fabricate an affirmation which it then postpones until the end of time’’. Therefore, Camus claims it is completely nihilistic for Russian revolution to stop man do anything but follow in the footsteps of the history in order to meet the ends.  The legacy of the Russian revolution is maintained, says Camus, only by “denying, to the advantage of history, both nature and beauty and by depriving man of the power of passion, doubt, happiness, and imaginative invention-in a word, of his greatness’’. The most interesting word in this sentence is ‘’doubt’’. Because unity encourage doubt and ensures that there is possibility of error, hence the word ‘doubt’’ supposes unity. On the other hand, totality finishes the doubt of the word ‘doubt’ for it supposes that everything is going in a historical condition and there is no possibility of error. Beside, when we look at the condition of rebellion, it is based on solidarity and solidarity encourages communication while this communication is based on doubt. There is no certainty and people are encouraged to work, cooperate and hear others towards the overcoming of an unwanted situation.  However, this doubt shall pave the path for the work to be done; it doesn’t stop the rebel acting on behalf of the people and their human condition. Camus’s character, Kaliayev, who is ‘the purest image of rebellion’ is doubtful of his action but yet takes responsibility of his actions and completes the mission.  In the absence of doubt, the Russian revolution changed its form into what Christian faith defined by St Ignatius in his Spiritual Exercises say: “We should always be prepared, so never to err, to believe that what I see as white is black, if the hierarchic Church defines it thus’’.

In addition, Camus says if rebellion had found a philosophy, it would be based on “philosophy of limits”. For instance, the rebel stands up against injustice, it does not mean that he has an idea of eternal justice, but because he wants to break that hostility that encourages silence between the oppressor and the oppressed.  Similarly and yet in contrast, the Russian revolution does not bear indifference to the human condition, it wants its advantages over the common sense of every member of his nation, although denying the fact that the human condition or perhaps the national condition might not be same for every member and considers the later the rivalry of their interests. A legitimate revolutionary act says Camus, is uncomprising since its means are concerned but yet accepts its limit. The errors of contemporary revolution “are first of all explained by the ignorance or systematic misconception of that limit’’ which is revealed by rebellion.

Absolute freedom denies justice and absolute justice denies freedom, it becomes, however, fruitful for both if they find in each the limit of the other.  Camusian believe that this reconciliation between justice and freedom take Camus the Greek concept of sophrosyene. This is one of the four cardinal virtues defined by Plato in his book, The Republic, which means ‘’moderation’’ or ‘’temperance’’. It relates to interpret all kinds of experience-whether moral, political, aesthetic, physical or metaphysical-in terms of harmony and proportion.  In Homer, it is associated with modesty and consciousness of one’s limitations, in Theognis of Megara, it is related to the absence of overbearing pride and presumption, and in Aeschylean tragedy, it is linked with a set of desirable qualities, including justice and freedom and is opposed to hubris. In the same way, in his book, The Rebel, Camus replaces his Sisyphus with Aeschylus’s Prometheus.  Camus says the myth of Prometheus is not defined by hubris, not “of a universal struggle between good and evil’’ but is “a dispute about what is good’’.  And Prometheus being the hero of Camus’s rebellion finds its validity in its insistence upon limits and these limits that are put upon the consequence of the absurd: “The Absurd’’, Camus notes in Myth of Sisyphus, is “lucid reason noting its limits’’.  

Summing Up Camus

In conclusion, Albert Camus’s nuanced stance on the Algerian War of Independence reflects a profound tension between his identity as a pied-noir and his commitment to justice and human dignity. Born in Algeria and deeply influenced by its Mediterranean culture, Camus found himself in a paradoxical position, advocating for the rights of Algerians while being part of the European community often seen as the oppressors. Despite this, he maintained a steadfast dedication to a humanist vision that sought to transcend cultural and political boundaries, grounded in his belief in the principles of internationalism and the inherent dignity of man.

Camus’s efforts to advocate for the Algerian people were multifaceted and courageous. He supported the extension of French citizenship and voting rights to Algerian Muslims and condemned the systemic injustices they faced under French rule. His manifesto, denouncing the crushing poverty and lack of education among Algerians, highlighted his deep empathy and commitment to their cause. This was not merely a call for assimilation but a genuine plea for the recognition and restoration of the dignity of the Arab masses.

His expulsion from the Algerian Communist Party further illustrates his complex position. Camus’s support for pro-Arab militants and his subsequent fallout with the party, when it ceased backing these militants under Soviet directives, demonstrate his unwillingness to compromise on his principles, even at the cost of political isolation. His critique of the French administration’s ignorance and neglect, and his call for a civil truce to reduce the bloodshed, underscore his consistent push for a humanitarian solution to the conflict.

Contrary to postcolonial critics like Edward Said and Cruise O’Brien, Camus’s contemporaries, such as Amar Ouzegane and Albert Memmi, recognized his unique and empathetic stance. Memmi, in particular, appreciated the difficult position Camus found himself in—caught between the suspicions of the colonized, the indignation of left-wing French intellectuals, and the anger of his own community. Memmi’s characterization of Camus as the "colonizer of good will" captures the inherent ambiguity and moral complexity of his role.

Camus’s vision for Algeria was rooted in the principles of rebellion and unity, as opposed to the totalitarianism he saw in the Soviet model. He argued that rebellion should be based on solidarity and communication, acknowledging doubt and error as part of the process, rather than the absolute certainty demanded by totality. His call for a civil truce was a pragmatic approach aimed at creating conditions for dialogue and reducing the violence that plagued both sides of the conflict.

Ultimately, Camus’s legacy is not that of a simple colonizer or a detached intellectual, but of a deeply empathetic and principled figure navigating the intricate realities of colonial and postcolonial Algeria. His work and life exemplify the struggle to balance personal identity with universal human rights, making his contributions to the discourse on justice and rebellion profoundly relevant. Camus’s call for a balance between justice and freedom, embodied in the Greek concept of sophrosyne, remains a powerful reminder of the importance of moderation, empathy, and principled action in the pursuit of a just society.

 


Previous Post Next Post